Bulletin Board Pix
The Open Society and Its Enemies Open Society Popper
Table of Contents
- Preface To The First Edition
- Preface To The Second Edition
- Acknowledgements
- Introduction
- Volume I: The Spell Of Plato
- The Myth Of Origin And Destiny
- Chapter 1: Historicism And The Myth Of Destiny
- Chapter 2: Heraclitus
- Chapter 3: Plato’s Theory Of Forms Or Ideas
- Plato’s Descriptive Sociology
- Chapter 4: Change And Rest
- Chapter 5: Nature And Convention
- Plato’s Political Programme
- Chapter 6: Totalitarian Justice
- Chapter 7: The Principle Of Leadership
- Chapter 8: The Philosopher King
- Chapter 9: Aestheticism, Perfectionism, Utopianism
- The Background Of Plato’s Attack
- Chapter 10: The Open Society And Its Enemies
- Volume II: The High Tide of Prophecy
- The Rise Of Oracular Philosophy
- Chapter 11: The Aristotelian Roots Of Hegelianism
- Chapter 12: Hegel And The New Tribalism
- Marx’s Method
- Chapter 13: Marx’s Sociological Determinism
- Chapter 14: The Autonomy Of Sociology
- Chapter 15: Economic Historicism
- Chapter 16: The Classes
- Chapter 17: The Legal And The Social System
- Chapter 18: The Coming Of Socialism
- Chapter 19: The Social Revolution
- Chapter 20: Capitalism And Its Fate
- Chapter 21: An Evaluation Of The Prophecy
- Chapter 22: The Moral Theory Of Historicism
- The Aftermath
- Chapter 23: The Sociology Of Knowledge
- Chapter 24: Oracular Philosophy And The Revolt
Against Reason
- Conclusion
- Chapter 25: Has History Any Meaning?
- Notes
- Addenda to Volume I
- I. Plato And Geometry (1957)
- II. The Dating Of The Theaetetus (1961)
- III. Reply To A Critic (1961)
- IV. (1965)
Addenda to Volume II
- I. Facts, Standards, And Truth: A Further Criticism
Of Relativism (1961)
- II. Note On Schwarzschild’s Book On Marx (1965)
- Index Of Names
- Index Of Subjects
- Index Of Platonic Passages
Introduction
I do not wish to hide the fact
that I can only look with repugnance upon the puffed-up
pretentiousness of all these volumes filled with wisdom,
such as are fashionable nowadays. For I am fully
satisfied that the accepted methods must endlessly
increase these follies and blunders, and that even the
complete annihilation of all these fanciful achievements
could not possibly be as harmful as this fictitious
science with its accursed fertility. — KANT.
This book raises issues
which may not be apparent from the table of contents. It sketches some of the
difficulties faced by our civilization—a civilization which
might be perhaps described as aiming at humaneness and
reasonableness, at equality and freedom; a civilization
which is still in its infancy, as it were, and which
continues to grow in spite of the fact that it has been so
often betrayed by so many of the intellectual leaders of
mankind. It attempts to show that this civilization has not
yet fully recovered from the shock of its birth—the
transition from the tribal or ‘closed society’, with its
submission to magical forces, to the ‘open society’ which
sets free the critical powers of man. It attempts to show
that the shock of this transition is one of the factors that
have made possible the rise of those reactionary movements
which have tried, and still try, to overthrow civilization
and to return to tribalism. And it suggests that what we
call nowadays totalitarianism belongs to a tradition which
is just as old or just as young as our civilization itself.
It tries thereby to contribute
to our understanding of totalitarianism, and of the
significance of the perennial fight against it.
It further tries to examine the
application of the critical and rational methods of science
to the problems of the open society. It analyses the
principles of democratic social reconstruction, the
principles of what I may term ‘piecemeal social engineering’
in opposition to ‘Utopian social engineering’ (as explained
in Chapter 9). And it tries to clear away some of the
obstacles impeding a rational approach to the problems of
social reconstruction. It does so by criticizing those
social philosophies which are responsible for the widespread
prejudice against the possibilities of democratic reform.
The most powerful of these philosophies is one which I have
called historicism. The story of the rise and influence of
some important forms of historicism is one of the main
topics of the book, which might even be described as a
collection of marginal notes on the development of certain
historicist philosophies. A few remarks on the origin of the
book will indicate what is meant by historicism and how it
is connected with the other issues mentioned.
Although I am mainly interested
in the methods of physics (and consequently in certain
technical problems which are far removed from those treated
in this book), I have also been interested for many years in
the problem of the somewhat unsatisfactory state of some of
the social sciences and especially of social philosophy.
This, of course, raises the problem of their methods. My
interest in this problem was greatly stimulated by the rise
of totalitarianism, and by the failure of the various social
sciences and social philosophies to make sense of it.
In this connection, one point
appeared to me particularly urgent.
One hears too often the
suggestion that some form or other of totalitarianism is
inevitable. Many who because of their intelligence and
training should be held responsible for what they say,
announce that there is no escape from it. They ask us
whether we are really naive enough to believe that democracy
can be permanent; whether we do not see that it is just one
of the many forms of government that come and go in the
course of history. They argue that democracy, in order to
fight totalitarianism, is forced to copy its methods and
thus to become totalitarian itself. Or they assert that our
industrial system cannot continue to function without
adopting the methods of collectivist planning, and they
infer from the inevitability of a collectivist economic
system that the adoption of totalitarian forms of social
life is also inevitable.
Such arguments may sound
plausible enough. But plausibility is not a reliable guide
in such matters. In fact, one should not enter into a
discussion of these specious arguments before having
considered the following question of method: Is it within
the power of any social science to make such sweeping
historical prophecies? Can we expect to get more than the
irresponsible reply of the soothsayer if we ask a man what
the future has in store for mankind? This is a question of
the method of the social sciences. It is clearly more
fundamental than any criticism of any particular argument
offered in support of any historical prophecy.
A careful examination of this
question has led me to the conviction that such sweeping
historical prophecies are entirely beyond the scope of
scientific method. The future depends on ourselves, and we
do not depend on any historical necessity. There are,
however, influential social philosophies which hold the
opposite view. They claim that everybody tries to use his
brains to predict impending events; that it is certainly
legitimate for a strategist to try to foresee the outcome of
a battle; and that the boundaries between such a prediction
and more sweeping historical prophecies are fluid. They
assert that it is the task of science in general to make
predictions, or rather, to improve upon our everyday
predictions, and to put them upon a more secure basis; and
that it is, in particular, the task of the social sciences
to furnish us with long-term historical prophecies. They
also believe that they have discovered laws of history which
enable them to prophesy the course of historical events. The
various social philosophies which raise claims of this kind,
I have grouped together under the name historicism.
Elsewhere, in The Poverty of Historicism, I have tried to
argue against these claims, and to show that in spite of
their plausibility they are based on a gross
misunderstanding of the method of science, and especially on
the neglect of the distinction between scientific prediction
and historical prophecy. While engaged in the systematic
analysis and criticism of the claims of historicism, I also
tried to collect some material to illustrate its
development. The notes collected for that purpose became the
basis of this book.
The systematic analysis of
historicism aims at something like scientific status. This
book does not. Many of the opinions expressed are personal.
What it owes to scientific method is largely the awareness
of its limitations: it does not offer proofs where nothing
can be proved, nor does it pretend to be scientific where it
cannot give more than a personal point of view. It does not
try to replace the old systems of philosophy by a new
system. It does not try to add to all these volumes filled
with wisdom, to the metaphysics of history and destiny, such
as are fashionable nowadays. It rather tries to show that
this prophetic wisdom is harmful, that the metaphysics of
history impede the application of the piecemeal methods of
science to the problems of social reform. And it further
tries to show that we may become the makers of our fate when
we have ceased to pose as its prophets. In tracing the
development of historicism, I found that the dangerous habit
of historical prophecy, so widespread among our intellectual
leaders, has various functions. It is always flattering to
belong to the inner circle of the initiated, and to possess
the unusual power of predicting the course of history.
Besides, there is a tradition that intellectual leaders are
gifted with such powers, and not to possess them may lead to
loss of caste. The danger, on the other hand, of their being
unmasked as charlatans is very small, since they can always
point out that it is certainly permissible to make less
sweeping predictions; and the boundaries between these and
augury are fluid. But there are sometimes further
and perhaps deeper motives for holding historicist beliefs.
The prophets who prophesy the coming of a millennium may
give expression to a deep-seated feeling of dissatisfaction;
and their dreams may indeed give hope and encouragement to
some who can hardly do without them. But we must also
realize that their influence is liable to prevent us from
facing the daily tasks of social life. And those minor
prophets who announce that certain events, such as a lapse
into totalitarianism (or perhaps into ‘managerialism’), are
bound to happen may, whether they like it or not, be
instrumental in bringing these events about. Their story
that democracy is not to last for ever is as true, and as
little to the point, as the assertion that human reason is
not to last for ever, since only democracy provides an
institutional framework that permits reform without
violence, and so the use of reason in political matters. But
their story tends to discourage those who fight
totalitarianism; its motive is to support the revolt against
civilization. A further motive, it seems, can be found if we
consider that historicist metaphysics are apt to relieve men
from the strain of their responsibilities. If you know that
things are bound to happen whatever you do, then you may
feel free to give up the fight against them. You may, more
especially, give up the attempt to control those things
which most people agree to be social evils, such as war; or,
to mention a smaller but nevertheless important thing, the
tyranny of the petty official.
I do not wish to suggest that
historicism must always have such effects. There are
historicists—especially the Marxists—who do not wish to
relieve men from the strain of their responsibilities. On
the other hand, there are some social philosophies which may
or may not be historicistic but which preach the impotence
of reason in social life, and which, by this
anti-rationalism, propagate the attitude: "either follow the
Leader, the Great Statesman, or become a Leader yourself,"
an attitude which for most people must mean passive
submission to the forces, personal or anonymous, that rule
society. Now it is interesting to see
that some of those who denounce reason, and even blame it
for the social evils of our time, do so on the one hand
because they cannot conceive of a social science, or of
reason in society, having another function but that of
historical prophecy. In other words, they are disappointed
historicists; they are men who, in spite of realizing the
poverty of historicism, are unaware that they retain the
fundamental historicistic prejudice—the doctrine that the
social sciences, if they are to be of any use at all, must
be prophetic. It is clear that this attitude must lead to a
rejection of the applicability of science or of reason to
the problems of social life—and ultimately, to a doctrine of
power, of domination and submission.
Why do all these social
philosophies support the revolt against civilization? And
what is the secret of their popularity? Why do they attract
and seduce so many intellectuals? I am inclined to think
that the reason is that they give expression to a deep-felt
dissatisfaction with a world which does not, and cannot,
live up to our moral ideals and to our dreams of perfection.
The tendency of historicism (and of related views) to
support the revolt against civilization may may be due to
the fact that historicism itself is, largely, a reaction
against the strain of our civilization and its demand for
personal responsibility.
These last allusions are
somewhat vague, but they must suffice for this introduction.
They will later be substantiated by historical material,
especially in the chapter ‘The Open Society and Its
Enemies’. I was tempted to place this chapter at the
beginning of the book; with its topical interest it would
certainly have made a more inviting introduction. But I
found that the full weight of this historical interpretation
cannot be felt unless it is preceded by the material
discussed earlier in the book. It seems that one has first
to be disturbed by the similarity between the Platonic
theory of justice and the theory and practice of modern
totalitarianism before one can feel how urgent it is to
interpret these matters. |